Sidebilder
PDF
ePub

When it is not expressed, it may be inferred, implied, or presumed, from circumstances as really existing; and then the contract, thus ascertained, is called an implied one. The instances given by Blackstone are an

illustration of this.

"But it appears in another place, 3 Comm. 159-166, that Blackstone introduces this thought about reason and justice dictating contracts, in order to embrace, under this definition of an implied contract, another large class of relations which involve no intention to contract at all, though they may be treated as if they did. Thus, whenever, not our variant notions of reason and justice, but the common sense and common justice of the country, and therefore the common law or statute law, impose upon any one a duty, irrespective of contract, and allow it to be enforced by a contract remedy, he calls this a case of implied contract. Thus out of torts grows the duty of compensation, and in many cases the tort may be waived, and the action brought in assumpsit.

"It is quite apparent, therefore, that radically different relations are classified under the same term; and this must often give rise to indistinctness of thought. And this was not at all necessary; for we have another well-authorized technical term exactly adapted to the office of making the true distinction. The latter class are merely constructive contracts, while the former are truly implied ones. In one case, the contract is mere fiction, a form imposed in order to adapt the case to a given remedy; in the other, it is a fact legitimately inferred. In one, the intention is disregarded; in the other, it is ascertained and enforced. In one, the duty defines the contract; in the other, the contract defines the duty."

[ocr errors]

Yet the learned Justice, after so intelligently criticising Blackstone, falls into the same confusion of statement when he says, in the same opinion:1

"The law ordinarily presumes or implies a contract whenever this is necessary to account for other relations found to have existed between the parties.

"Thus if a man is found to have done work for another, and there appears no known relation between them that accounts for such service the law presumes a contract of hiring. But if a man's house takes fire, the law does not presume or imply a contract to pay his neighbors for their services in saving his property. The common principles of human conduct mark self-interest as the motive of action in the one case, and kindness in the other; and therefore, by common custom, compensation is mutually counted on in one case, and in the other not."

[graphic]

1 Hertzog v. Hertzog, 29 Pa. St. 465, 468.

Plainly, in the case put by Mr. Justice Lowrie, the inference of a contract is one of fact; and in another part of the same opinion the learned Justice clearly regards the inference as one of fact and not one of law, when he says:1

66

Every induction, inference, implication, or presumption in reasoning of any kind, is a logical conclusion derived from and demanded by certain data or ascertained circumstances. If such circumstances demand the conclusion of a contract to account for them, a contract is proved; if not, not. If we find, as ascertained circumstances, that a stranger has been in the employment of another, we immediately infer a contract of hiring, because the principles of individuality and self-interest, common to human nature, and therefore the customs of society, require the inference."

In the opinion of Lord Justice Lindley, it was the failure of Lord Justice Brett to recognize the distinction in question, which led him to doubt 2 that a lunatic was liable for necessaries furnished to him, by one knowing of his lunacy. On this point Lord Justice Brett expressed himself as follows:

"A question has been flushed, if I may use the word, in this case which it is not necessary to decide, namely, whether if a person supplies necessaries to a lunatic, knowing of the lunacy at the time, a contract on the part of the lunatic to pay for them can be implied. I give no opinion upon that point. It has not been fully argued to-day, and it appears to me to involve a very difficult point of law, which I do not think has ever been settled by authority. For my part I should doubt whether in favor of a person who knows of the lunacy you can imply a contract to pay for a supply of necessaries to a lunatic."

3

In Rhodes v. Rhodes, Lord Justice Lindley, referring to the doubt raised by Lord Justice Brett, said :

"The question whether an implied obligation arises in favor of a person who supplies a lunatic with necessaries is a question of law, and In re Weaver, a doubt was expressed whether there is any obligation on the part of the lunatic to repay. I confess I cannot participate in that doubt. I think that that doubt has arisen from the unfortunate terminology of our law, owing to which the expression 'implied contract' has been used to denote, not only a genuine contract established by inference, but also an obligation which does not arise from any real contract,

1 Hertzog v. Hertzog, 29 Pa. St. 465, 469.

* In re Weaver, 21 Ch. D. 615-620.

44 Ch. D. 94, 107.

but which can be enforced as if it had a contractual origin. Obligations of this class are called by civilians obligationes quasi ex contractu.”

It was this confusion of ideas that caused the counsel in Sceva v. True,1 to contend, that as an insane person was not able to contract, the defendant was not liable for necessaries furnished to her by one knowing her to be insane. The counsel's argument in that case was as follows:

one.

"The foundation principle of the entire law of contract is, that the parties must have the capacity to contract, and must actually exercise their faculties by contracting. Here there was no capacity, for there was but one mind; no contract was made, and no attempt was made to make The two vital facts, without which no contract, tacit or express, can exist, capacity and its exercise, are wanting. Was there an implied contract? What does that term mean? In thousands of cases, in the books, we know just what it means. The parties have capacity to contract; facts, circumstances, few or many, clear or complicated, exist, which lead the minds of the jurors to the conclusion that the minds of the parties met. Minds may meet by words, acts, or both. The words even may negative such meeting; but acts which speak louder than words' may conclude him who denies a tacit contract. Aside from cases where the capacity to contract is wanting, no instance now occurs to us in which the implied contract cannot be supported upon these principles, and the familiar doctrines of waiver and estoppel. . . It is another fundamental principle that no one, by voluntarily performing services for another, can make the other his debtor. If these principles apply to cases where the contracting mind is wanting, they settle this case. We know it is sometimes said, in such a case, 'the law will imply a contract.' What does that mean? As it seems to us, only this: that where A, who has capacity to contract, furnishes B, who is totally destitute of such capacity, what is proper for B to have, the judges will turn the bench into a broker's board, will substitute themselves for B, make a contract where none existed, cause it to relate back to the voluntary acts of A, and then sit in judgment upon and enforce their own contract. It is a perversion of language to call such a performance a contract of any kind. It is judicial usurpation. The Constitution gave the court no such power. The court has no power to make contracts for people: it can only infer one where a jury might."

To this argument the court made the following conclusive

answer:

1 1 53 N. H. 627.

"We regard it as well settled by the cases referred to in the briefs of counsel, many of which have been commented on at length by Mr. Shirley for the defendant, that an insane person, an idiot, or a person utterly bereft of all sense and reason by the sudden stroke of accident or disease, may be held liable, in assumpsit, for necessaries furnished to him in good faith while in that unfortunate and helpless condition. And the reasons upon which this rests are too broad, as well as too sensible and humane, to be overborne by any deduction which a refined logic may make from the circumstances that in such cases there can be no contract or promise in fact, no meeting of the minds of the parties. The cases put it on the ground of an implied contract; and by this is not meant, as the defendant's counsel seems to suppose, an actual contract, that is, an actual meeting of the minds of the parties, an actual mutual understanding, to be inferred from language, acts, and circumstances, by the jury, but a contract and promise, said to be implied by the law, where, in point of fact, there was no contract, no mutual understanding, and so no promise. The defendant's counsel says it is usurpation for the court to hold, as matter of law, that there is a contract and a promise, when all the evidence in the case shows that there was not a contract, nor the semblance of one. It is doubtless a legal fiction, invented and used for the sake of the remedy. If it was originally usurpation, certainly it has now become very inveterate, and firmly fixed in the body of the law."1

[ocr errors]

Not only has this identification in classification of quasi-contracts with genuine contracts led to a confusion of ideas, but it has also rendered the interpretation of written laws or statutes exceedingly difficult where the word "contract" is used; thus, for example, in Dusenbury v. Speir,2 the legality and arrest turned upon the meaning to be given to the phrase "contract express or implied," as used in statutes regulating arrests in civil actions. The plaintiff had been arrested in an action, corresponding to the common-law action, of money had and received, brought to recover money which the plaintiff, the defendant in that action, had fraudulently obtained. The plaintiff was arrested on a warrant issued on the theory that the action was that of contract, express or implied, within the meaning of the statute. It was held that his liability was in quasicontract, and not in contract, and that as the phrase "contract express or implied" was used in the statutes with reference solely to genuine contracts, the arrest was illegal, and the judgment of

1 Illustrations of this confusion of ideas might be multiplied indefinitely; but it seems unnecessary to cite them here, as further illustrations will be offered in the discussion of the scope of quasi-contract.

377 N. Y. 144.

the lower court was reversed. And yet the court, whose judgment was reversed by the Court of Appeals, recognized as fully as did the Court of Appeals that the obligation to return the money was a quasi-contractual, and not a contractual, obligation.1

In O'Brien v. Young, the question involved was the construction of the statute reducing the rate of interest from seven per cent to six per cent. The statute contained a clause excepting from its operations "any contract or obligation made before the passage of this Act." It was contended that a judgment obtained before the passage of the Act was exempted from its operations, and that the judgment creditor was, therefore, entitled to six per cent interBut the court reversed the judgment of the lower court, holding that the clause in question referred, not to quasi-contracts, but to genuine contracts only, and that, therefore, the judgment creditor was entitled to only six per cent after the passage of the Act.

est.

3

But in The Gutta Percha Shoe Co. v. Mayor, etc., it was held that although a judgment was not a genuine contract, yet an

1 Probably no clearer statement of the distinction between a genuine contract and a quasi-contract can be found than is contained in the following statement, taken from the opinion of Mr. Justice Danforth in this case:

"We cannot agree with the learned judge in this construction of the statute. On the contrary, we think that the express contract referred to in the statute is one which has been entered into by the parties, and upon which, if broken, an action will lie for damages, or is implied, when the intention of the parties, if not expressed in words, may be gathered from their acts and from surrounding circumstances; and in either case must be the result of the free and bona fide exercise of the will, producing the aggregatio mentium, the joining together of two minds, essential to a contract at common law. There is a class of cases where the law prescribes the rights and liabilities of persons who have not in reality entered into any contract at all with one another, but between whom circumstances have arisen which make it just that one should have a right, and the other should be subject to a liability, similar to the rights and liabilities in certain cases of express contract. Thus, if one man has obtained money from another through the medium of oppression, imposition, extortion, or deceit, or by the commission of a trespass, such money may be recovered back, for the law implies a promise from the wrong-doer to restore it to the rightful owner, although it is obvious that is the very opposite of his intention. Implied or constructive contracts of this nature are similar to the constructive trusts of courts of equity, and in fact are not contracts at all. And a somewhat similar distinction is recognized in the civil law, where it is said: 'In contracts it is the consent of the contracting parties which produces the obligation; in quasi-contracts there is not any consent. The law alone, or natural equity, produces the obligation by rendering obligatory the fact from which it results. Therefore these facts are called quasi-contracts, because, without being contracts, they produce obliga. tions in the same manner as actual contracts.'"

[graphic]

295 N. Y. 428.

8 108 N. Y. 276.

« ForrigeFortsett »