Sidebilder
PDF
ePub

66

be

straight line which has a given ratio to the other segment, may equal to a given space;" instead of which problem I have substituted this other : To divide a given straight line so that the rectangle "under its segments may be equal to a given space." In the actual solution of problems, the greater generality of the former proposition is an advantage more apparent than real, and is fully compensated by the simplicity of the latter, to which it is always easily reducible.

[ocr errors]

The same may be said of the 29th, which Euclid enunciates thus : "To a given straight line to apply a parallelogram equal to a given "rectilineal figure exceeding by a parallelogram similar to a given "parallelogram." This might be proposed otherwise: "To pro"duce a given line, so that the parallelogram having in it a given angle, and contained by the whole line produced, and a straight line "that has a given ratio to the part produced, may be equal to a given "rectilineal figure." Instead of this, is given the following problem, more simple, and, as was observed in the former instance very little less general. "To produce a given straight line, so that the rectangle "contained by the segments, between the extremities of the given line, and the point to which it is produced, may be equal to a given space."

66

PROP. A, B, C, &c.

Nine propositions are added to this Book on account of their utility and their connection with this part of the Elements. The first four of them are in Dr. Simson's edition, and among these Prop. A is given immediately after the third, being, in fact, a second case of that proposition, and capable of being included with it, in one enunciation. Prop. D. is remarkable for being a theorem of Ptolemy the Astronomer, in his Meyaλn Zuvrağıs, and the foundation of the construction of his trigonometrical tables. Prop. E is the simplest case of the former; it is also useful in trigonometry, and, under another form, was the 97th, or, in some editions, the 94th of Euclid's Data. The propositions F and G are very useful properties of the circle, and are taken from the Loci Plani of Apollonius. Prop. H is a very remarkable property of the triangle; and K is a proposition which, though it has been hitherto considered as belonging particularly to trigonometry, is so often of use in other parts of the Mathematics, that it may be properly ranked among the elementary theorems of Geometry.

SUPPLEMENT.

TH

BOOK I.

PROP. V and VI, &c.

HE demonstrations of the 5th and 6th propositions require the method of exhaustions, that is to say, they prove a certain property to belong to the circle, because it belongs to the rectilineal figures inscribed in it, or described about it according to a certain law, in the case when those figures approach to the circles so nearly as not to fall short of it, or to exceed it by any assignable difference. This principle is general, and is the only one by which we can possibly compare curvilineal with rectilineal spaces, or the length of curve lines with the length of straight lines, whether we follow the methods of the ancient or of the modern geometers. It is therefore a great injustice to the latter methods to represent them as standing on a foundation less secure than the former; they stand in reality on the same, and the only difference is, that the application of the principle, common to them both, is more general and expeditious in the one case than in the other. This identity of principle, and affinity of the methods used in the elementary and the higher mathematics, it seems the more necessary to observe, that some learned mathematicians have appeared not to be sufficiently aware of it, and have even endeavoured to demonstrate the contrary. An instance of this is to be met with in the preface of the valuable edition of the works of Archimedes, lately printed at Oxford. In that preface, Torelli, the learned commentator, whose labours have done so much to elucidate the writings of the Greek Geometer, but who is so unwilling to acknowledge the merit of the modern analysis, undertakes to prove, that it is impossible, from the relation which the rectilineal figures inscribed in, and circumscribed about, a given curve, have to one another, to conclude any thing concerning the properties of the curvilineal space itself, except in certain circumstances which he has not precisely described. With this view he attempts to shew, that if we are to reason from the relation which certain rectilineal figures belonging to the circle have to one another, notwithstanding that those figures may approach so near to the circular spaces within which they are inscribed, as not to differ from them by any assignable magnitude, we shall be led into error, and shall seem to prove, that the circle is to the square of ite

diameter exactly as 3 to 4. Now, as this is a conclusion which the discoveries of Archimedes himself prove so clearly to be false, Torelli argues, that the principle from which it is deduced must be false also; and in this he would no doubt be right, if his former conclusion had been fairly drawn. But the truth is, that a very gross paralogism is to be found in that part of his reasoning, where he makes a transition from the ratios of the small rectangles, inscribed in the circular spaces, to the ratios of the sums of those rectangles, or of the whole rectilineal figures. In doing this, he takes for granted a proposition, which, it is wonderful, that one who had studied geometry in the school of Archimedes, should for a moment have supposed to be true. The proposition is this: If A, B, C, D, E, F, be any number of magnitudes, and a, b, c, d, e, f, as many others; and if A: B:: a: b,

C: D :: c: d,

E : F :: ef, then the sum of A, C and E will be to the sum of B, D and F. as the sum of a, c and e, to the sum of b. d and ƒ, or A+ C+E B+D+F :: a+c+e : b+d+f. Now, this proposition, which Torelli supposes to be perfectly general, is not true, except in two cases, viz. either first, when A Ca: c,

:

and

A: Eae; and consequently,
B: D:: b :d, and

B: F:: b :f; or, secondly, when

all the ratios of A to B, C to D, E to F, &c. are equal to one another. To demonstrate this, let us suppose that there are four magnitudes, and four others,

thus A B a: b, and

C: D :: cd, then we cannot have A+C: B+D::a+c: b+d, unless either, A: C:: a: c, and B : Dbd; or A: C :: b: d, and consequently a b c : d.

K, A, B, L,

Take a magnitude K, such that a:c: A: K, and another L, such that bd B: L; and suppose it true, that A+C : B+D::a+c:b+d. Then, because by inversion ; K: A ca, and, by hypothesis, A: B:: a: b, and also B Lb d, ex æquo, K: L::c:d; and consequently, K: L:: C: D.

[ocr errors]

Again, because A: K::a: c, by addition,

C a. b d.

A+K: Ka+c: c; and, for the same reason,
B+L:L::b+d: d, or, by inversion,

L: B+L::d: b+d. And, since it has been shewn,

that K: L:: cd; therefore ex æquo,

A+K, K, L, B+L.

atc, c, d, b d.

A+K : B+L :: a+c: b+d; but by hypothesis,

A+C B+D :: a+c : b+d, therefore

A+K: A+C :: B+L:B+D.

[ocr errors]

::

Now, first, let K and C be supposed equal, then it is evident, that L and D are also equal; and therefore, since by construction a: c:: A: K, we have also a : c :: A: C; and, for the same reason, 6 : d : B: D, and these analogies form the first of the two conditions, of which one is affirmed above to be always essential to the truth of Torelli's proposition.

Next, if K be greater than C, then since

A+K: A+C: B+L:B+D, by division,

A+K: K-C:: B+L:L-D. But, as was shewn
K: L:: C: D, by conversion and alternation,
K-C:K::L-D: L, therefore, ex æquo,
A+K:K ::B+L : L, and lastly, by division,
AK BL, or A; B:: K: L, that is,
A: BC: D.

Wherefore, in this case the ratio of A to B is equal to that of C to D, and consequently, the ratio of a to b equal to that of c to d. The same may be shewn, if K is less than C; therefore in every case there are conditions necessary to the truth of Torelli's proposition, which he does not take into account, and which, as is easily shewn, do not belong, to the magnitudes to which he applies it.

In consequence of this, the conclusion which he meant to establish respecting the circle, falls entirely to the ground, and with it the general inference aimed against the modern analysis.

It will not, I hope, be imagined, that I have taken notice of these circumstances with any design to lessen the reputation of the learned Italian, who has in so many respects deserved well of the mathematical sciences, or to detract from the value of a posthumous work, which by its elegance and correctness, does so much honour to the English editors. But I would warn the student against that narrow spirit which seeks to insinuate itself even into the abstractions of geometry, and would persuade us, that elegance, nay truth itself, are possessed exclusively by the ancient methods of demonstration. The high tone in which Torelli censures the modern mathematics, is imposing, as it is assumed by one who had studied the writings of Archimedes with uncommon diligence. His errors are on that account the more dangerous, and require to be the more carefully pointed out.

PROP. IX.

This enunciation is the same with that of the third of the Dimensio Circuli of Archimedes ;' but the demonstration is different. though it proceeds, like that of the Greek Geometer, by the continual bisection of the 6th part of the circumference.

The limits of the circumference are thus assigned; and the method of bringing it about, notwithstanding many quantities are neglected in the arithmetical operations, that the errors shall in one case be all on the side of defect, and in another all on the side of excess, (in which I have followed Archimedes,) deserves particularly to be observed, as affording a good introduction to the general methods of approximation.

BOOK II.

DEF. VIII. and PROP. XX.

SOLID angles, which are defined here in the same manner as in Euclid, are magnitudes of a very peculiar kind, and are particularly to be remarked for not admitting of that accurate comparison, one with another, which is common in the other subjects of geometrical investigation. It cannot, for example, be said of one solid angle, that it is the half, or the double of another solid angle, nor did any geometer ever think of proposing the problem of bisecting a given solid angle. In a word, no multiple or sub-multiple of such an angle can be taken, and we have no way of expounding, even in the simplest cases, the ratio which one of them bears to another.

In this respect, therefore a solid angle differs from every other magnitude that is the subject of mathematical reasoning, all of which have this common property, that multiples and sub-multiples of them may be found. It is not our business here to inquire into the reason of this anomaly, but it is plain, that on account of it, our knowledge of the nature and the properties of such angles can never be very far extended, and that our reasonings concerning them must be chiefly confined to the relations of the plane angles, by which they are contained. One of the most remarkable of those relations is that which is demonstrated in the 21st of this Book, and which is, that all the plane angles which contain any solid angle must together be less than four right angles. This proposition is the 21st of the 11th of Euclid.

A

This proposition, however, is subject to a restriction in certain cases, which, I believe, was first observed by M. le Sage of Geneva, in a communication to the Academy of Sciences of Paris in 1756. When the section of the pyramid formed by the planes that contain the solid angle is a figure that has none of its angles exterior, such as a triangle, a parallelogram, &c. the truth of the proposition just enunciated cannot be questioned. But, when the aforesaid section is a figure like that which is annexed, viz. ABCD, having some angles, such as BDC, exterior, or, as they are sometimes called, re-entering angles, the proposition is not necessarily true; and it is plain, that in such cases the demonstration which we have given, and which is the same with Euclid's, will no longer apply. Indeed, it were easy to shew, that on bases of this kind, by multiplying

B

D

the number of sides, solid angles may be formed, such that the plane

« ForrigeFortsett »