Sidebilder
PDF
ePub

V.-DEAF AND DUMB.

HISTORY OF THEIR INSTRUCTION, IN REFERENCE
TO DALGARNO.

(JULY, 1835.)

The Works of GEORGE DALGARNO, of Aberdeen, 4to. Reprinted at Edinburgh: 1834.

IN taking up this work, we owe perhaps some apology for the deviation from our ordinary rules; inasmuch as it is merely a reprint of ancient matter, the publication also not professedly reaching beyond the sphere of a private society,—the Maitland Club. We are induced, however, to make a qualified exception in favour of this edition of Dalgarno's Works, in consideration of the extreme rarity of the original treatises, added to their high importance; and because the liberality of the editors, (Mr Henry Cockburn and Mr Thomas Maitland), has not limited their contribution merely to members of that society, but extended it to the principal libraries of the kingdom, and, we believe, to many individuals likely to feel an interest in its contents. We shall, however, relax our rule only to the measure of a very brief notice.

Dalgarno's Works are composed of two treatises: the first entitled " Ars Signorum, Vulgo Character Universalis et Lingua Philosophica. Londini: 1661;" the second-" Didascalocophus, or the Deaf and Dumb Man's Tutor; to which is added a Discourse of the Nature and Number of Double Consonants: both which Tracts being the first (for what the Author knows) that have been published upon either of the subjects. Printed at the Theatre in Oxford, 1680."

Of the author himself, all that is now known is comprised in

the following slight notice by Anthony a Wood. "The reader may be pleased to know, that one George Dalgarno, a Scot, wrote a book entitled, Ars Signorum, &c., London, 1661. This book, before it went to press, the author communicated to Dr Wilkins, who, from thence taking a hint of greater matter, carried it on, and brought it up to that which you see extant. This Dalgarno was born at Old Aberdeen, and bred in the University at New Aberdeen; taught a private grammar school, with good success, for about thirty years together, in the parishes of S. Michael, and S. Mary Mag., in Oxford; wrote also Didascalocophus, or the Deaf and Dumb Man's Tutor; and dying of a fever, on the 28th of August, 1687, aged sixty or more, was buried in the north body of the church of S. Mary Magdalen." (Athenæ Oxon., Vol. II., p. 506.) With the exception of an accidental allusion to his treatise on Signs, by Leibnitz, in a letter to Mr Burnet of Kemney, from whom he had probably received that work of a fellow Aberdonian, and some slight traditionary statements by the German historians of literature, the memory of Dalgarno had wholly perished, when attention was again awakened to the originality and importance of his speculations by the late Mr. Dugald Stewart, in various passages of his writings; and these having suggested to the editors the idea of the present reprint, they are very properly collected in their preliminary statement, as the best of testimonies to its importance.

In speaking of Dalgarno's two treatises, we shall reverse their chronological as well as natural order, and take them in what appears to us the order of their practical interest.

To appreciate the high and peculiar value of our author's treatise on the education of the Deaf and Dumb, it is necessary to take a survey of what had actually been accomplished in this important department of applied psychology, previous to the appearance of his treatise. A regular history of this branch of education, with extracts from the writings of its earlier promoters, now in general extremely rare, would form an interesting present, both to the speculative and to the practical philosopher. In the total absence of such a work, we may be pardoned in throwing briefly together a few scattered notices, which have accidentally crossed us in the course of other inquiries.

In deducing a history of the progress in the art of educating the Deaf and Dumb, there are certain separate points of accomplishment which it is proper to distinguish. These are: 1°,

from Syllogism proper; wrong in all the particulars of the

contrast.

But that the Philosopher is not in error, is evident at once; whereas the Archbishop's doctrine is palpably suicidal. On that doctrine, the inductive reasoning is “a syllogism in Barbara, the major premiss being always substantially the same:- What belongs to the individual or individuals we have examined, belongs to the whole class under which they come."

Now, we ask:-In what manner do we obtain this major, in the evolution of which all Induction consists? Here there are only four possible answers.-1°, This proposition, (like the dictum de omni et de nullo, and the axiom of the convertibility of the whole and its parts,) it may be said, is (analytically) selfevident, its negation implying a contradiction. This answer is manifestly false. For so far from being necessitated by the laws of thought, it is in opposition to them; the whole of the consequent not being determined in thought by the some of the antecedent.-2°, It may be said to be acquired by Induction. This, however, would be absurd; inasmuch as Induction itself is, ex hypothesi, only possible, through and after the principle it is thus adduced to construct. This of the proposition as a whole. The same is also true of its parts. "Class" is a notion, itself the result of an Induction; it cannot, therefore, be postulated as a pre-requisite or element of that process itself. A similar remark applies to "property.”—3°, It may be said to be deduced from a higher axiom. What then is such axiom? That has not been declared. And if such existed, the same questions would remain to be answered regarding the higher proposition which are now required in relation to the lower.-4°, It may be asserted to be (as Kant would say, synthetically) given as an ultimate principle of our intellectual constitution. This will not do. In the first place, if such principle exist, it only inclines, it does not necessitate. In the second, by appealing to it, we should transcend our science, confound the logical and formal with the metaphysical and material. In the third, we should thus attempt to prove a logical law from a psychological observation; i.e. establish an a priori, a necessary science on a precarious experience, an experience admitted perhaps by the disciples of Reid and Royer-Collard, but scouted by those of Gassendi and Locke.*

"It is by induction that all axioms are known, such as:- Things that are equal to the same are equal to one another;' 'A whole is greater than its parts;'

Logicians, we already observed, have been guilty of a fundamental error, in bringing the distinction of perfect and of imperfect Induction within the sphere of their science, as this distinction proceeds on a material, consequently on an extralogical difference. In this error, however, Dr Whately exceeds all other logicians, recognising, as he does, exclusively, that Induction, which is only precariously valid, and valid only through an extralogical presumption. This common major premise, if stated as necessary, is (formally and materially) false; if stated as probable, it is (formally) illegitimate, even if not (materially) untrue, both because an inferior degree of certainty is incompatible with an apodictic science, and because the amount of certainty itself must, if not capriciously assumed, be borrowed from evidence dependent on material conditions beyond the purview of a formal science.

Dr Whately is not less unfortunate in refuting the opinions of other logicians touching Induction, than in establishing his

own.

"In this process," he says, "we are employing a syllogism in Barbara with the major premiss suppressed; not the minor, as Aldrich represents it. The instance he gives will sufficiently prove this :-This, that, and the other magnet, attract iron; therefore so do all.' If this were, as he asserts, an enthymeme whose minor is suppressed, the only premise which we could supply to fill it up would be, 'all magnets are this, that, and the other;' which is manifestly false." (P. 217.)

Aldrich has faults sufficient of his own, without taking burden of the sins of others. He is here singly reprehended for saying only what, his critic seems not aware, had been said by all logicians before him. The suppressed minor premise even obtained in the schools the name of the Constantia; and it was not until the time of Wolf* that a new-fangled doctrine, in this respect the same as Whately's, in some degree superseded the older and correcter theory. "In the example of Aldrich," says our author, "the suppressed minor premiss, all magnets are and all other mathematical axioms." Huyshe, p. 132. The same doctrine is held by Hill, p. 176.—Is such the Oxford Metaphysic? [This doctrine, the ingenious author of "The Regeneration of Metaphysics" (pp. 81, 104), charges also on Dr Whately.]

* [I said generally "the time of Wolf;" for I recollected that some German logicians, prior to him, had held the same doctrine. It was however Wolf's authority which rendered the innovation general.-M. Peisse has here the following note :-"The germ of this doctrine is to be found in Gassendi. (Inst. Log. Pars iii. canon 11. Opera, i. 113.)"]

this, that, and the other,' is manifestly false." Why?—Is it because the proposition affirms that a certain three magnets (“this, that, and the other") are all magnets? Even admitting this, the objection is null. The logician has a perfect right to suppose this or any other material falsity for an example; all that is required of him is, that his syllogism should be formally correct. Logic only proves on the hypothetical truth of its antecedents. As Magentinus notices, Aristotle's example of Induction is physiologically false; but it is not on that account a whit the worse as a dialectical illustration. The objection is wholly extralogical.-But this is not, in fact, the meaning of the proposition. The words (in the original "hic, et ille, et iste magnes") are intended to denote every several magnet. Aldrich borrows the instance from Sanderson, by whom it is also more fully expressed :-"Iste magnes trahit ferrum, et ille, et hic, et pariter se habet in reliquis," &c.-Perhaps, however, and this is the only other alternative, Dr Whately thinks the assumption "manifestly false," on the ground that no extent of observation could possibly be commensurate with "all magnets." This objection likewise lies beyond the domain of the science. The logician, qua logician, knows nothing of material possibility and impossibility. To him all is possible that does not involve a contradiction in terms. At the same time, the present is merely the logical manner of wording the proposition. The physical observer asserts on the analogy of his science, "This, that, the other magnet, &c., represent, all magnets;" which the logician accepting, brings under the conditions, and translates into the language of his "This, that, the other magnet, &c., are all magnets," i.c. are conceived as constituting the whole-Magnet.

Dr Whately's errors relative to Induction are, however, surpassed by those of another able writer, Mr Hampden, in regard both to that process itself, and to the Aristotelic exposition of its nature;-errors the more inconceivable, as he professes to have devoted peculiar attention to the subject, which he says, "deserves a more particular notice, as throwing light on Aristotle's whole method of philosophising, while it shows how far he approximated to the induction of modern philosophy." His words

are:

"To obtain an accurate notion of the being of anything, we' require a definition of it. A definition of the thing corresponds, in dialectic, with the essential notion of it in metaphysics. This abstract notion, then, accord

« ForrigeFortsett »